“That’s just the
way I am!” How many times have we heard
that when someone we know or have met tries to justify acting in a way that is
thoroughly obnoxious and unacceptable?
We might here this variation: “That’s the way I was brought up” or
something similar. We are supposed to
accept this person’s behavior, no matter how much it violates social norms,
because we should presume that he or she cannot help but act this way. After all, we would not criticize someone
with a disability because he could not do something with the same ease as a
person without the disability, would we?
We have an obligation, we are told, to be non-judgmental and accept this
person, warts and all, because it is a part of his genetic or environmental
make-up.
Do we really have
such an obligation? More importantly,
are we merely the captive puppets of our genetic or our environmental
heritage? To what extent, if any, are we
free to modify our attitudes and behavior?
These questions go to the heart of our social order, to our very concept
of right and wrong. The notion of
correction or punishment presumes that we are, at least at some level,
responsible for our own behavior. So,
for that matter, does the belief that the object of the justice system should
be reform or rehabilitation. If a person
is responsible for his actions, then he can change. If he can change, then he is responsible. At some level all of us believe that people
are responsible for what they do. We may
talk about how we should consider mitigating circumstances and so forth, but
that is usually when we have no personal interest in the behavior in question. It usually becomes a completely different
matter when we are the object of some objectionable behavior.
A pundit once
described a conservative as a liberal who has been mugged, and there is some
real truth to this observation. It is,
according to the implication, one thing to express an opinion about criminal
behavior when we are only disinterested observers. It can matter much more to us when we are the
victims, and it usually does. We might
read in the newspaper about a young man who has robbed a convenience
store. If he is from a poor home, or was
raised by a single mother, or fits into one of any number of politically
correct categories, you can be sure that he will have many people who will come
to his defense because of these circumstances.
They may not argue that he should be acquitted entirely because of
them—although some will—but they will insist that the courts consider them when
it comes to the matter of punishment.
Watch what happens,
however, when this same fountain of compassion and understanding becomes the
victim of a crime. Now, everything is
different. Now, we must uphold the
law. Now, the criminal must be
punished! This is natural because we all
really do, beneath it all, believe that we are responsible for what we say and
do. When I become the victim instead of
being an observer, that elemental feeling comes out. Here is a common example of this
phenomenon. In many African-American
communities, the people have no trust or confidence in the agents of law
enforcement. This may stem from any number
of reasons, but it is nonetheless true. Many commentators and pundits have complained
about the fact that the penalties for the sale or possession of powder cocaine
are less that those for the same offenses involving crack cocaine. There should be no surprise here: powder
cocaine tends to be used by whites, and crack by African-Americans. A disinterested observer might feel justified
in labeling this as just another example discriminatory law enforcement. Is it mere coincidence that the crime more
likely to be committed by African-Americans carries a harsher penalty than the
similar crime more likely to be committed by whites?
Here is the
surprise. The penalties for both forms
of cocaine used to be the same, but the demand for harsher penalties came, not
from people in law enforcement, or from the white community, but from people in
the African-American communities that were being ravaged by crack use. Powder cocaine was far too expensive to be in
common use among members of the African-American community, which tends to be
poorer than the average white community.
However, the crystal form of the drug delivered a more powerful reaction
for much less money, and its social effects were horrendous. The members of the community demanded action
and the government responded. Was the
response right or wrong? For the purpose
of this essay that question is completely irrelevant. What matters is this: when its interests were
involved, the African-American community became as much a law and order
community as any suburban white community.
We see two significant phenomena here.
Those who demanded harsh penalties for crack use were making a 180
degree shift in their attitude towards law enforcement. They also showed that, at least on this
issue, they were unwilling to accept any touchy-feely excuses for criminal
behavior.
So, we can all be
put into situations where we demonstrate our belief that people are responsible
for their actions, notwithstanding any mitigating factors. However, to be honest we must ask one
question. Are we merely, when faced with
matters that touch us personally, reverting to a more primitive emotion? Perhaps our reactions when we are truly
disinterested are more accurate. After
all, many times this is the case. This
may be true, but what is important is the underlying principle: we can, given
sufficient encouragement, change our opinions and attitudes about different
things.
How so? I’ll give you an example from my own life,
one that I have used elsewhere. I have
always been terrified of heights, even to this day. My wife and I owned a condominium apartment
on the 10th floor of our building.
I had to go out on to the balcony if I wanted to have a cigarette. As long as I sat or stood away from the rail
I was alright, but if I even thought about going near the edge, my knees would
buckle. I mean that literally; I could
be sitting inside our unit and, if I just imagined leaning over the edge, my
knees would get weak. So, with this
image clear in you mind, imagine this.
When I was at my ROTC summer camp, I was faced with this task. We had to climb to the top of a fifty foot
tower that had a metal cable stretched out over a rather deep creek. The cable ran down to a ten foot pole at the
other end. From the top of the tower, we
were required to grab a sliding bar and slide down the cable to the other
end. Ten feet before the end, we had to
let go and drop into the water, while moving about 20 miles per hour. If you didn’t let go, you would slam into the
pole and be rather seriously injured.
That was not
all. As soon as we were finished we had
to jog over to a second tower. This was
on the edge of one side of the creek, and there was a matching tower on the
other side. Stretched between the two
towers was a thick rope about twenty to twenty-five feet above the water. We had to crawl out onto the rope, let go
with one hand, salute, and ask permission to drop in the water. When that was granted, we let go and dropped
into the creek. For someone with a
previously debilitating fear of heights, these events looked like they would be
almost as much fun as catching the bubonic plague. In short, I was terrified of the prospect of
having to complete these events. What
motivated me to do them was a conflicting emotion: pride. I was about seven years older than most of
the other ROTC cadets. They had only
completed their third year of college, while I was in graduate school. In addition, I had already served three years
in the Army, rising to the specialist equivalent of sergeant. The cadre and the younger cadets expected me
to set an example for them, and I was determined not to let them down. So, I charged up the towers, all the while
yelling with my best imitation of a Viking berserker. To be honest, I think that I was trying to
convince myself to go through with these events. Anyway, I fooled the cadre and the other
cadets; they were astounded to find out later just how scared I had been. This is, however, the definition of courage,
to do something in spite of your fear.
The point is that I was motivated by another emotion that was stronger
than my fear, and it demonstrates that even deep-seated emotions can be
overcome.
This clearly means
that we are not the prisoners of our past.
Here are two more personal examples.
My wife is from Guatemala;
she was born and grew up there. One of
her parents was Asian, and the other was German. She, however, is thoroughly Latina
in her outlook and attitudes, because that was the common culture of her
society. After years in the United
States, she took me to visit her
family. They told her that she had
become too American! She had, of course,
absorbed much of American ways of living.
My own heritage is a mix of Scottish, English and Swedish, but except
for my admiration of the English legal heritage, I don’t identify with any of
those cultures. My house looks like a
Greek or Roman temple; as I write this I have votive candles burning to images
of Apollo, the Lares and Penates, and Fortuna Primigenia. As far as I know, I have no Greek or Italian
ancestry, but I admire these cultures for the foundations they laid down for
modern Western humanist civilization.
It seems to me
that, ultimately, we are what we want to be, not what we inherited through our
genes or absorbed through our environment.
We become that which we admire, that which we want to emulate. We see this phenomenon in cases of religious
conversion. Augustine was a libertine
who had dabbled in Manichean religion and Neo-Platonist philosophy; he had
refused any dealing with his mother’s Christianity. After his conversion he became one of the
most important figures in Christian theology, at least up until Thomas
Aquinas. This effect can be found in
converts to many religions, not just Christianity. We know of the case of Malcolm X, who turned
from a criminal life when he joined the Nation of Islam. Drug addicts have kicked their habits because
they started worshipping Krishna. These events are perfectly genuine; these
converts truly internalize new values and beliefs.
This does not
imply, nor should the reader infer, that the objects of such religious devotion
are real in any objective sense. As a
secular philosopher I would be skeptical of any such claims, but that is not
what is important. What matters is that
the convert believes that the claims are real.
He or she could have decided to worship Marduk or the snake god of the
Marsi people of pre-Roman Italy. It is the sincerity of the conversion and the
intensity of the belief that matter. As
long as the believer is sincere, the personality or behavior change required by
his or her new faith will occur. It is
the motivation that matters, not the reality behind that motivation.
This does not
address the original issue, however.
Yes, our beliefs, actions and attitudes can change, given sufficient
motivation, but to say that they can change is not the same as to say that they
should be expected to change. The
ability to change does not imply the obligation to do so. To clarify the issue, let’s create a
hypothetical scenario. Our protagonist,
John, has an attitude that society owes him a comfortable standard of living.
Furthermore, he tends to express this attitude in ways that interfere with
holding a good job and making friends; he has “a chip on his shoulder.” How did he come by this attitude? That really doesn’t matter. Perhaps he grew up in an upper class home
where he could have the best of everything, and he has become so used to this
that he thinks it is some kind of birthright.
His parents may have had to work for their prosperity, but since that is
all he knows, he thinks of it as something he should just have. Or, perhaps he grew up in a very poor family
and has come to think that the larger society owes some kind of debt to
him. In his situation, it is clear that
something is going to have to change; either John is going to have to adapt to
the expectations of others, or they are going to have to adapt to him.
Of course, there is
a third option: nobody makes any changes, and John remains miserable. Let’s assume that this is not an option, because
John is not happy in his current state.
We may ask, why does he have any obligation to change his behavior? Why does no one have to adapt to him? If what I have argued previously is true,
that we have no positive obligations to others unless we are in some sort of
special, personal relationship, why is there this obligation on John’s
part? It is simply this: none of the
rest of us—those who comprise the “general society” that John resents—have any
positive obligations that would require us to alter our own attitudes towards
John. As long as we leave him alone in a
kind of benign neglect—in short, as long as we do him no harm—we have fulfilled
our only obligations. We have no
positive duties to alter our attitudes or expectations to suit his needs. We can simply go about our daily lives as we
wish, even if that action leaves him in the same rut he was in to begin with.
So, if John does
not want to remain miserable, and if we have no obligation to accommodate him,
what is left but for him to make whatever changes to his attitude and behavior
that are necessary to change his external situation? Epictetus gave an example in his Discourses
about a man who came to him complaining about how his brother was treating him;
he asked Epictetus for his advice.
Epictetus replied that he could help the man behave properly towards his
estranged brother, but there was nothing he could say to the man about changing
the brother’s behavior. For that, he
replied, bring your brother to me, and I will speak with him. As to his behavior, however, I have nothing
to say to you. In short, Epictetus was
teaching, in true Stoic fashion, that while we control our own thoughts and
behavior, we cannot control another’s behavior.
John can alter his own behavior and attitudes, but there is nothing he
can do about the external world. If
there is something about his life that he does not like, it is up to John to
make the necessary changes.
In this example we
have talked about a man whose personality, for whatever reason, contained a
serious flaw. Here is the politically
incorrect ramification of this argument.
Suppose that John’s problem is not a personality flaw, but that he is
from a different country and culture. In
this case John’s problem is that behavior that would have been totally
acceptable in his own country is considered completely inappropriate in his new
home. Does this new circumstance make
any difference in our conclusion? I
think that logic forces us to conclude that it does not do any such thing. Let’s give the example some specific
details. John is now an American
businessman working at his company’s office in Germany. He speaks very little German, just enough to
get by on the street. He doesn’t think
that he needs to, since they use English at the office since it is only a
branch of an American firm. He finds
out, to his chagrin, that he has alienated some of his German neighbors, who
think that he is rude. What could have
happened?
Well, if we look at
the German language, we will notice something interesting. In English we have only one word for the
second person pronoun, “you,” and we use it for all circumstances. German, on the other hand, has two forms,
“du” and “Sie.” The first form is used
with children, family members and very close personal friends. “Sie” is used in all other
circumstances. In English we would say
“you” when referring to our spouse, boss or total stranger. In German, no one would ever use “du” when
speaking to a boss or stranger. It would
be considered insulting, and inappropriately familiar. German society is much more formal than
American society, and the language reflects that formality.
In John’s case, it
turns out that he has been using the word “du” rather than “Sie” to his
neighbors. Furthermore, he has been
behaving with typical American casualness, addressing his neighbors by their
first name rather than has “Herr” or “Frau.”
This was, when I was there anyway, considered gauche. So, what should our friend John do? I think we all know that his neighbors are going
to expect him to be the one who has to make any cultural adaptations. They are not going to remake German society
simply to make an American business executive happy. It is simply the old saying, “When in Rome,
do as the Romans.” Again, it is going to
be the responsibility of the individual to make any adjustments that have to be
made. This principle applies just as
strongly to an immigrant to America
as it does to an American who lives elsewhere.
Here is an example
of an event that happened several years ago in Washington,
D.C.
A young man who was an immigrant from one of the Latin American
countries was arrested for public intoxication and for resisting arrest. The second charge was filed after he fought
the policewoman who responded to the complaint.
After the arrest, some members of the community tried to excuse the
young man’s actions. First, they
defended his conduct on the grounds that drinking in front of one’s house—even
in public—with one’s friends was not a serious matter in the young man’s home
country. Second, they complained that
the police department had been “insensitive” in sending an African-American
female to arrest him. They should have
sent a male officer, according to the protestors, because a young Hispanic male
would have been humiliated to be arrested by a woman.
It is quite clear
that this young man, not the police force or any of the other agencies of government,
is the one who was wrong, and he was wrong on two counts. First, it may be true that drinking in public
with his friends might have been acceptable behavior in his home country, or it
might not be true. Either way, that
argument is meaningless. He was not in
his home country, he was in the capital of the United
States of America, and different rules apply
in different countries. Second, in would
be absurd to expect our government to reinforce prejudices just because they
were acceptable overseas. It was the
young man’s responsibility to change his behavior because it was in his power
to do so. It was not in his power to
change the rules here.
We should note that
we are always free to refuse to alter our behavior in order to fit in with
others, but then we cannot expect to be listened to if we complain that we are
being ostracized. That would be as
foolish as expecting to lose excess weight on a diet of cheeseburgers and
french fries. It would simply not
happen. It is not a matter of morality,
but one of practicality. If I am not
willing to spend the time practicing, I will never learn to play the piano, at
least much beyond “Chopsticks.” If I do
not exercise, I will never become much of an athlete. It is a simple, practical matter of cause and
effect. If fitting in with others is my
goal, then I must do what it takes to accomplish that goal. This does not mean, however, that adapting to
others is always the right thing to do.
As a Stoic, I would
caution the reader that popularity, or being liked, is never a worthy
goal. It might even be an immoral goal,
depending upon the circumstances. The
Stoic goal is to achieve peace of mind by conforming one’s desires to nature,
by desiring only those things that are under our control. “Being liked by others” is simply not
something that is within our control. We
can do what we can to be likeable, but that doesn’t mean that others will like
us. What if everyone in your
neighborhood is a jerk? We can certainly
prefer to be liked rather than disliked.
If the gods came down to me and said, “It is in your hands. You can be liked or disliked, with no changes
or effort on your part. Which do you
prefer?” Well, duh…What do you think I
would choose? The problem is that, last
time I checked, the gods have not offered me that choice.
There are times and
circumstances in which adapting to the local cultural norms would actually be
immoral, not just futile. If the local
customs are in some way evil, then it would be a wrong act even to make the
effort to fit in. We must never forget
that our highest values are to be faithful to what is true and to do what we
see as right. We should consider
Socrates’ example. He did not choose to
“fit in” with all of the customs in Athens. In fact, he chose instead to be loyal to what
he saw as the truth, even though it cost him his life. He could have chosen to blend in with the
rest of the Athenian citizens, but if he had, who would have remembered
him? He was purple stripe on the toga
praetexta, the mark of dignity, not the white of the bulk of the garment.
The focus of this
essay is not to encourage the reader to sacrifice his moral purpose in order to
be popular. That would be as immoral as
it would be stupid. It would be immoral
because we should never sacrifice our values for transient gain. It would be stupid because we do not control
other peoples’ beliefs or opinions, so why compromise a goal that is within our
power for one that is not? We might
choose to sacrifice our principles in order to become popular, only to find
that not only did we not become popular, but now we can’t stand to look at
ourselves in the mirror. Having said
that, we can certainly admit that when there are no moral issues involved,
there is nothing at all wrong with wanting to be a good neighbor. Much of what constitutes neighborliness has
little or no real moral content; it is simply a matter of accepting and
respecting local customs. I am a native
of Northern Virginia, a suburb of Washington
D.C. that has become quite
cosmopolitan. I recently moved to a
semi-rural area north of Atlanta, Georgia. There are certainly some differences between
life in these two areas, but none of them, at least as far as I can tell,
involve any moral issues. Life certainly
is more casual here, but casualness is neither a vice nor a virtue. That being the case, there is certainly no
reason for me to try to avoid blending in as much as possible.
For example, the
first day we moved in I made a point of raking the yard and gathering up the
leaves. Our new house had been vacant
for several months, so we wanted to get the yard looking as nice as we
could. We planted some flowers and two
crepe myrtles. We did this right away so
that the neighbors could see that the new owners had every intention of being
responsible, constructive members of our new community. If there was any moral issue involved, it was
that every member of a community should be productive and useful. On the other hand, if we had moved to an area
whose customs required that I violate one or more deeply held principles, then
it would have been my duty to refuse to cooperate. Suppose that I had moved here 60 years ago,
and the local custom demanded that everyone who is eligible join the Ku Klux
Klan. That would have been an immoral
act, and it would have been a right act to refuse to join. However, that is certainly no longer the
case. As you could guess, this is a more
religious region than Northern Virginia, at least in
terms of church membership and attendance, but it is not some American version
of Taliban Afghanistan. We may have businesses that refuse to open on
Sunday for religious reasons, but no one is forced to attend any church.
There are some
obvious limits to accommodating local customs.
My accent gives me away every time I open my mouth. I happen to think that Jeff Foxworthy is one
of the funniest comedians in America—now I am even living in his home state—but
I can guarantee you that I sound nothing like him. If I were to say “y’all” instead of “you” it
would sound phony. It would sound so
phony that it would probably come across as condescending. I like country music, but I never wear a
baseball cap. I like to fish—even though
I’m not that good at it—but forget hunting.
There is no way that I could pass as a native of Georgia,
so it is better not even to try.
These are only surface
differences; the conservative attitudes here still evoke a sense of patriotism
and duty that are missing farther north, and I find these appealing. Farther north you are likely to find people
who seem to be ashamed of being American.
The people here seem prouder of being American, and they are more likely
to share traditional values. The
important point is that I don’t expect anybody to make any adjustments for
me. I do expect to be left alone on
those matters where we differ, but I have no right to expect people to adapt to
my customs, no matter where I live. I
lived in Germany
for four years during the time I was in the Army. Even though we were there as a part of NATO,
and defending Germany
from the Soviet Union was a part of our mission, we were
taught that we were expected to learn and respect German customs; they were not
expected to learn ours.
Obviously some
solders were better at this than others.
We would have soldiers who would walk in a German Gasthaus and be told
that the establishment was full, even though they could see a free table. These soldiers would complain that the local
merchants were discriminating against them, but they would be wrong. Invariably, the table that they thought was
“free” was the Stammtisch, a table reserved for regular customers. One could only sit at this table by
invitation, and this rule applied to Germans as much as it did Americans. If the proprietor were, in fact,
discriminating against some American soldiers because of race or religion, then
the commander would have had the option of placing the establishment
“off-limits.” This would have meant that
no military personnel would be permitted to patronize the business, and this
was a threat that was often quite effective.
If, however, the soldiers had been turned away for a legitimate reason,
such as rowdy behavior or if the Stammtisch was the only available space, then
nothing would be done. Actually, the
soldiers would probably be counseled on their need to learn and understand the
local customs! Eventually most soldiers
learned to respect the local practices, because there were really only two
choices: adapt and enjoy one’s tour in Germany,
or refuse to adapt and spend the entire time complaining about life overseas.
In all of life this
is really the ultimate choice, isn’t it?
The Stoic message has always been that our happiness is in our own
hands. If we are in a crowd, we can
complain that everything is noise and commotion, or we can act as if we were in
the middle of a celebration and enjoy the party. If we are alone, we can complain that we have
nothing to do, no one to talk to, or we can regard it as peace and solitude,
and enjoy the opportunity to read and think.
In all our dealings with others we must react the same way. As long as we do not have to compromise our
ethical beliefs, we can adapt to the local mores and participate in the local
life. The option is to complain that
“they” are strange, or backwards, or whatever, and live miserable, crabbed
lives.
It is really both
simple and logical. If we want others to
accept us, we must be the ones who are willing to make the effort. We will never have any control over the
actions of others, especially of their opinions of us. If we live our lives in accordance with our
principles—assuming our principles are admirable—we may induce other people to
respect us, but that does not mean that they will like us. No matter what the reason that we may find
ourselves alienated from our neighbors, whether that reason be our personality,
our cultural heritage, or whatever, we must make the effort to be
“likeable.” If, in a given situation
that is our desire, then we, not they, must make the effort.
No comments:
Post a Comment