Martin Buber was known for his definition of relationship as falling into one of two categories, I and Thou and I and It. The latter is the way we should look at material objects, inanimate tools: home, car, computer, and so forth. Human relations, he felt, should always fall into the I and Thou category, which mirrors the relationship he felt we should have with God. People are never things, and we should never treat people as things.
However, he was wrong, at least in this way: In his book The Secular City, Harvey Cox argues that we should NOT want all human relationships to be of a deep interpersonal nature. True, that does not mean that we treat another person as a tool for our happiness, but he felt the dichotomy was false. For example, he writes about his relationship with his TV repairman. Yes, he says, I should treat him like a fellow human being. No, I do not want to have much contact with him, because, if I do, it means that my television is broken and seeing him will cost me money! We have a mutually respectful business relationship, and there is no moral obligation to make it personal in any way. He called this type of relationship I and You.
Now, my own categories of general and special relationship do not falls into this scheme, but Cox's analysis does show that there are many ways to look at the nature of social relationships, and that they need not fall into traditional paradigms to be valid.
Sunday, May 27, 2012
Wednesday, May 23, 2012
The Foundation of RIght and Wrong
In Stoic thought, we say that one of the choices we have that is within our control is our ability to act on our moral principles. Although we are never guaranteed success--that is an external and, hence, a "thing indifferent"--our actions are totally within our control. We can always choose to do the right thing in the given circumstances. But...what makes something right or wrong? In a purely naturalist philosophy, how do we determine what is ethical and what is not?
Start from this observation: in our relationships with others, there are two basic types of relationships. There are general relationships, those where we are simply aware of our shared humanity, where we have nothing more in common than the fact that we both exist. There are also what I call "special relationships," where we have entered into a voluntary association, such as a friendship, a business, or a marriage. These relationships will entail certain specific responsibilities, IF we wish to preserve them. It is sort of an if-then situation; IF I wish to maintain this friendship, THEN I will have to treat this person in a friendly way. If I do not do so, the friendship will be lost. In general relationships, on the other hand, all I am obligated to do is to leave the other person alone, to avoid infringing on his or her space.
There is another key observation we have to make. Philosophical and religious systems can be classified as falling into one of two types, along a continuum with these two ideals representing the opposite poles of the continuum. There are "perfectionist" moral systems, where we focus on improving our nature, so to speak, and "social" moral systems, where the goal is to define the rules that allow the society to function. In the latter, it does not matter what you think, only how you act. You could hate me, but as long as you do nothing harmful to me you have done no wrong, violated no laws.
Say that this other person, Joe, is riding a subway with me. My only obligation to him is to avoid bothering him. Our shared existence does not require anything further engagement. I am not responsible for Joe's happiness. I have no obligation to support him, take care of him, or do any other thing of an affirmative nature. Now, if he happens to be a friend, that would be a different matter, if I wish to "preserve the character of friend," to use Epictetus' phraseology.
This means that as naturalists we cannot affirm any form of Golden Rule or categorical imperative as least insofar as it might affirm positive duties to mankind as a whole. Negative duties, yes, because a social order cannot exist without them. Common sense tells us that a society that allowed anyone to simply take the property of another because he wanted it would not survive. Negative obligations are all that we can affirm, at least in relationships to strangers.
There is one other consideration for the Stoic, and that is this, and it is also along the "If, Then" model. If I wish to emulate the Stoic ideal, there may well be certain forms of behavior that are conducive to such a life, and simply logic may compel me to act in certain ways. But, these are not universal in their applicability.
Start from this observation: in our relationships with others, there are two basic types of relationships. There are general relationships, those where we are simply aware of our shared humanity, where we have nothing more in common than the fact that we both exist. There are also what I call "special relationships," where we have entered into a voluntary association, such as a friendship, a business, or a marriage. These relationships will entail certain specific responsibilities, IF we wish to preserve them. It is sort of an if-then situation; IF I wish to maintain this friendship, THEN I will have to treat this person in a friendly way. If I do not do so, the friendship will be lost. In general relationships, on the other hand, all I am obligated to do is to leave the other person alone, to avoid infringing on his or her space.
There is another key observation we have to make. Philosophical and religious systems can be classified as falling into one of two types, along a continuum with these two ideals representing the opposite poles of the continuum. There are "perfectionist" moral systems, where we focus on improving our nature, so to speak, and "social" moral systems, where the goal is to define the rules that allow the society to function. In the latter, it does not matter what you think, only how you act. You could hate me, but as long as you do nothing harmful to me you have done no wrong, violated no laws.
Say that this other person, Joe, is riding a subway with me. My only obligation to him is to avoid bothering him. Our shared existence does not require anything further engagement. I am not responsible for Joe's happiness. I have no obligation to support him, take care of him, or do any other thing of an affirmative nature. Now, if he happens to be a friend, that would be a different matter, if I wish to "preserve the character of friend," to use Epictetus' phraseology.
This means that as naturalists we cannot affirm any form of Golden Rule or categorical imperative as least insofar as it might affirm positive duties to mankind as a whole. Negative duties, yes, because a social order cannot exist without them. Common sense tells us that a society that allowed anyone to simply take the property of another because he wanted it would not survive. Negative obligations are all that we can affirm, at least in relationships to strangers.
There is one other consideration for the Stoic, and that is this, and it is also along the "If, Then" model. If I wish to emulate the Stoic ideal, there may well be certain forms of behavior that are conducive to such a life, and simply logic may compel me to act in certain ways. But, these are not universal in their applicability.
Monday, May 21, 2012
How do we know what we know?
Everything we know about the world comes from one source:
observations. They may be as systematic
as a laboratory science, or they may be totally anecdotal and unorganized. They may be personal observations, or they
may come from the observations of others who may—or, admittedly, may not—have
more expertise than we do. Nonetheless,
everything ultimately comes from some form of direct observation.
We do, of course,
also learn things by making extrapolations and interpolations from data. Mathematics and logic do play roles in
learning about nature, and we regularly make inferences—not all of them
justified—from what we have observed. We
also make completely non-rational conclusions about the world, and many of
these are correct; the activity of the right brain is inherently non-linear and
non-rational, like throwing a crossword puzzle into the air thousands of times
a minute until it lands in the correct order.
For any of these non-direct conclusions to be reliable, however, they
have to be testable by observed data. Without such testing, they are useless,
dogmatic proclamations.
We can work through
an example of how that process. I see
you standing in a field with a stone in your hand; you let go of the stone and
it falls to the ground. I learned from
this that, at one point in time you held this object, let it go, and it
fell. Technically, that is all I have
learned, that it happened once. Now, if
I see you do it several times, and if, every time, the stone falls to the
ground when you let it go, then I can conclude that when you let go of the
stone, it will fall to the ground. I am
curious, so I get other people to do the same thing and, wonder of wonders,
every single time someone holds a stone and lets it go, it falls to the
ground! Thinking I might be stumbling
upon something profound, I get people to hold different objects, not just
stones, and observe further that when any object is released, it falls to the
ground. I may not know the cause, but I
do see what happens: objects that are released from the hand, or any other way
they are supported, fall to the ground when that support is no longer
there. From this I deduce a general rule
that when objects are dropped they fall to the ground.
Here is an example
of how I can learn from a direct observation and, as well, from an
extrapolation from that data. If we look
closely, however, that “knowledge” I obtained from the extrapolation is not as
reliable as the information I obtained from the first observation. First, I have not, and cannot, observe every
single incidence of something being dropped; it is at least possible that my
universal conclusion is incorrect.
Furthermore, not only are my data incomplete, but I could interpret the
data incorrectly. Suppose in my
“experiment” I asked you to hold and drop a rock, and other person to hold and
drop a leaf at the same time. Sure, I
observe that they both fall to the ground as they had in the past, but I also
note that the rock hits the ground before the leaf does. Furthermore, whenever a leaf and a rock are
dropped together, the rock seems to fall faster.
What do I conclude
from this? I might conclude correctly
that it is the shape of the leaf that is causing it fall more slowly—air
resistance—or I might conclude, incorrectly, that it is weight that cause the
difference, that heavier objects fall faster than light ones. This
is, in fact, the error that people made, and this error was not corrected until
Galileo performed his famous experiments at the tower
of Pisa. If I do not have you drop two stones of the
same shape but different weights at the same time, I am likely to draw the
erroneous conclusion. So, we have to
admit these two caveats about empirical observation: a direct observation can be wrong if I did
not see what I thought I saw, but conclusions drawn from data can be wrong for
several other reasons as well. Direct
observation will only be incorrect if I observed incorrectly, but
extrapolations can be incorrect if any of the following occur: if I observe
incorrectly the data will be wrong, if I extrapolate too without sufficient
data, or if I make a failure in logic and reason improperly.
Suppose I did guess
the right reason. I am still likely to draw an improper conclusion, because I
might be tempted make the conclusion more universal than it really is. Unless I performed the experiment in a zero
gravity environment, or in a vacuum with no air resistance, or with objects
that would be subject to the same resistance, like two identically shaped
objects, I am unlikely to make the
proper connections, and come up with a wrong explanation about the data. A key part of explaining the data is to
understand the parameters of the experiment, and limiting the conclusion to the
variables of the experiment. Yes, the
conclusion will be limited, but the more limited, the more reliable.
As I mentioned
earlier, we cannot ignore the role that non-rational insight provides in
advancing knowledge. Collected data may
well tell us that a conclusion at which we arrived earlier was incomplete, or
even incorrect, but the data will not provide the new conclusion. That comes from insight, the “aha” factor. We examine the data, and in a moment of
insight, guess—and at this point it is still a guess—a new explanation. In religion we may assume that it was the
gods, or the spirits, that provided this new explanation, but empirical
research does not work that way.
Primitive people did not think that one would question or test the gods,
but modern man does. We don’t take this
insight on faith; we test it. We call
this insight an hypothesis, and subject it to repeat testing.
Most hypotheses
will fail the experiments devised to test them, and, even when they pass, the
results are published so that others may test them. Alternative explanations for the data are
welcomed, not condemned, so that all possibilities can be investigated. There is, unfortunately, always the
possibilities of honest error, tunnel vision and, sadly enough, outright
fraud. The antidote, of course, is the
kind of transparency that science considers the ideal. No question is ever considered to be finally
and completely answered. On all matters,
our conclusions are always tentative, always incomplete, and always open to
correction. There is no final, absolute
truth as far as we are concerned, only better and more accurate
conclusions. Common sense will tell us,
then, that if we want to avoid looking like fools, we should avoid making
absolute statements outside of the realm of mathematics and formal logic.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)